1. Po raz pierwszy odwiedzasz EDU. LEARN

    Odwiedzasz EDU.LEARN

    Najlepszym sposobem na naukę języka jest jego używanie. W EDU.LEARN znajdziesz interesujące teksty i videa, które dadzą Ci taką właśnie możliwość. Nie przejmuj się - nasze filmiki mają napisy, dzięki którym lepiej je zrozumiesz. Dodatkowo, po kliknięciu na każde słówko, otrzymasz jego tłumaczenie oraz prawidłową wymowę.

    Nie, dziękuję
  2. Mini lekcje

    Podczas nauki języka bardzo ważny jest kontekst. Zdjęcia, przykłady użycia, dialogi, nagrania dźwiękowe - wszystko to pomaga Ci zrozumieć i zapamiętać nowe słowa i wyrażenia. Dlatego stworzyliśmy Mini lekcje. Są to krótkie lekcje, zawierające kontekstowe slajdy, które zwiększą efektywność Twojej nauki. Są cztery typy Mini lekcji - Gramatyka, Dialogi, Słówka i Obrazki.

    Dalej
  3. Wideo

    Ćwicz język obcy oglądając ciekawe filmiki. Wybierz temat, który Cię interesuje oraz poziom trudności, a następnie kliknij na filmik. Nie martw się, obok każdego z nich są napisy. A może wcale nie będą Ci one potrzebne? Spróbuj!

    Dalej
  4. Teksty

    Czytaj ciekawe artykuły, z których nauczysz się nowych słówek i dowiesz więcej o rzeczach, które Cię interesują. Podobnie jak z filmikami, możesz wybrać temat oraz poziom trudności, a następnie kliknąć na wybrany artykuł. Nasz interaktywny słownik pomoże Ci zrozumieć nawet trudne teksty, a kontekst ułatwi zapamiętanie słówek. Dodatkowo, każdy artykuł może być przeczytany na głos przez wirtualnego lektora, dzięki czemu ćwiczysz słuchanie i wymowę!

    Dalej
  5. Słowa

    Tutaj możesz znaleźć swoją listę "Moje słówka", czyli funkcję wyszukiwania słówek - a wkrótce także słownik tematyczny. Do listy "Moje słówka" możesz dodawać słowa z sekcji Videa i Teksty. Każde z słówek dodanych do listy możesz powtórzyć później w jednym z naszych ćwiczeń. Dodatkowo, zawsze możesz iść do swojej listy i sprawdzić znaczenie, wymowę oraz użycie słówka w zdaniu. Użyj naszej wyszukiwarki słówek w części "Słownictwo", aby znaleźć słowa w naszej bazie.

    Dalej
  6. Lista tekstów

    Ta lista tekstów pojawia się po kliknięciu na "Teksty". Wybierz poziom trudności oraz temat, a następnie artykuł, który Cię interesuje. Kiedy już zostaniesz do niego przekierowany, kliknij na "Play", jeśli chcesz, aby został on odczytany przez wirtualnego lektora. W ten sposób ćwiczysz umiejętność słuchania. Niektóre z tekstów są szczególnie interesujące - mają one odznakę w prawym górnym rogu. Koniecznie je przeczytaj!

    Dalej
  7. Lista Video

    Ta lista filmików pojawia się po kliknięciu na "Video". Podobnie jak w przypadku Tekstów, najpierw wybierz temat, który Cię interesuje oraz poziom trudności, a następnie kliknij na wybrane video. Te z odznaką w prawym górnym rogu są szczególnie interesujące - nie przegap ich!

    Dalej
  8. Dziękujemy za skorzystanie z przewodnika!

    Teraz już znasz wszystkie funkcje EDU.LEARN! Przygotowaliśmy do Ciebie wiele artykułów, filmików oraz mini lekcji - na pewno znajdziesz coś, co Cię zainteresuje!

    Teraz zapraszamy Cię do zarejestrowania się i odkrycia wszystkich możliwości portalu.

    Dziękuję, wrócę później
  9. Lista Pomocy

    Potrzebujesz z czymś pomocy? Sprawdź naszą listę poniżej:
    Nie, dziękuję

Już 62 372 użytkowników uczy się języków obcych z Edustation.

Możesz zarejestrować się już dziś i odebrać bonus w postaci 10 monet.

Jeżeli chcesz się dowiedzieć więcej o naszym portalu - kliknij tutaj

Jeszcze nie teraz

lub

Poziom:

Wszystkie

Nie masz konta?

3. Introduction to Ancient Greek History: The Dark Ages (cont.)


Poziom:

Temat: Edukacja

Professor Donald Kagan: Our topic today is
the Dark Ages and the world of Homer,
and of course, you have as one of your reading
assignments a problem that deals precisely with that question
that asks the subordinate question: was there a real world
that Homer's poems refer to? If so, what world was it?
Was it the world of the Mycenaean Bronze Age?
Was it the world that succeeded that Bronze Age that we call the
Dark Ages? Was it the world in which
tradition says Homer himself lived, the transition first to
the Archaic and then to the Classical Period,
the period in which we think about the dawn of the
polis? That really is the question we
are wrestling with and, of course, behind it all is
this idea: can we seek any historical information from
Homer's poems at all? It would be a terrible blow to
me and everybody else in the field if the answer was "no,"
because just about everything we have to say about this period
between the Bronze Age and the emergence of the
polis--most of it involves inferences from our
understanding of what the Homeric poems tell us.
But I think we need to take a hard look at what we can do,
and I thought it would be worthwhile reading a sentence
from each of the introductory paragraphs that we provide for
you in the problem packet to show you the range of opinion
that is pretty representative of what scholars think or have
thought on the subject. Moses Finley says,
"If, then, the world of Odysseus is to be placed in time
as everything we know from the comparative study of heroic
poetry says it must, the most likely centuries seem
to be the tenth and the ninth, that is to say what we call the
Dark Ages." Anthony Andrews says,
"It may be that the epic tradition had at some stage used
as a model for the army before Troy,
an idealized version of some of those bands of colonists who
settled the coast of Asia Minor in post-Mycenaean times."
And if you look at the whole story that he tells,
that really means quite soon after the fall of the Mycenaean
world, probably maybe a century
earlier than what Finley suggests.
And then A.M. Snodgrass says,
"I offer this as a further argument against the existence
of a historical, Homeric society."
There isn't anything to be found is what Snodgrass says.
Ian Morris writes, "The balance of probability
seems to be in favor of a consistent basis to the society
of the poems derived from Greece in the eight century B.C.,"
which would be at the end of the period we've been talking
about, the transition to the world of the
polis--Homer's own time when he lived and wrote.
And finally, Barry Strauss says,
"Ironically, the more Homer exaggerates,
the more authentic he is as a representative of the Bronze
Age." So, what do we do?
Well, all of these are learned and clever men,
but I don't think that they're all equally right.
But what I should also report to you is that I think there is
a widespread consensus among most people that study the
subject. That doesn't mean that
consensus is correct. Not all of these opinions are
shared by the same number, by no means,
of scholars. Some of them are far out.
I would say the one that says you can't learn anything from
this is an outlier. The notion that this is about
the Mycenaean world is an outlier, and then I would say
the largest consensus is something like Finley's
consensus, but people verging in both
directions from that. What you'll hear from me is
essentially that consensus point of view.
It strikes me as being better supported than the others,
but we really have to keep an open mind because in this
prehistoric period, you have to be very modest
about what you think you know about it.
Almost everything is inference and judgment,
and very little is anything that you want to call proof.
With those warnings, let me tell you sort of what I
think most people think about this.
First of all, if we want to know about the
Dark Ages, what sources do we have available to us?
And of course, I've already mentioned the
poems of Homer turn out to be a very large source for what most
people look to. Secondly, there are legends
that the Greeks told about their early history,
which come down to us in later sources and they are available
to us to use as sources. A great question is,
should we use them at all, and if we do how carefully
should we use them and so on? This is a good time for me
to make a confession, so that you'll know how to
judge what I say all through the course.
Well, prior to the late eighteenth century when German
scholars began to look at the Homeric poems specifically,
very, very carefully, and then really very,
very skeptically, they made all sorts of
suggestions that the poems we have are really not to be
thought of as the work of a single poet,
Homer, who had--wrote them both out together.
But who began to divide them up into early and late elements,
which I thought drove the field of classics insane for about 100
years, while folks argued about the
unity of Homer, the unity or not the unity of
one of the poems and so on. But it began a critical study
of the poems for the first time and critical methods were
applied to history for the first time ever,
really, in the early nineteenth century and thereafter.
And it became common to reject any ancient story that wasn't
really nailed down very, very firmly by some device.
To take a skeptical view--and a very interesting
example of how things changed, if you look at people,
say an Englishman writing about Ancient Greece in the late
eighteenth century, they tell the story of the
early days based upon the legends as though the legends
were reliable information to some degree.
When you get to say the middle of the nineteenth century and
the work of the great English historian of Ancient Greece,
George Grote, he begins his story in 776 with
the Olympic Games. He does tell you all about the
legends first, but he puts them aside and says
they're just legends--now let's talk history,
and he doesn't begin that until the eight century B.C.
And so there is this critical school that says,
"I won't believe anything unless it is proven to me."
At the other extreme, there's me, the most gullible
historian imaginable. My principle is this.
I believe anything written in ancient Latin or Greek unless I
can't. Now, things that prevent me
from believing what I read are that they are internally
contradictory, or what they say is impossible,
or different ones contradict each other and they can't both
be right. So, in those cases I abandon
the ancient evidence. Otherwise, you've got to
convince me that they're not true.
Now, you might think of this as, indeed,
gullible. A former colleague of mine put
the thing very, very well.
He spoke about, and I like to claim this
approach, the position of scholarship to which we call the
higher naiveté.
The way this works is, you start out,
you don't know anything, and you're naïve.
You believe everything. Next, you get a college
education and you don't believe anything, and then you reach the
level of wisdom, the higher naiveté,
and you know what to believe even though you can't prove it.
Okay, be warned; I'm a practitioner of the
higher naiveté. So, I think the way to deal
with legends is to regard them as different from essentially
sophisticated historical statements,
but as possibly deriving from facts, which have obviously been
distorted and misunderstood, misused and so on.
But it would be reckless, it seems to me,
to just put them aside and not ask yourself the question,
"Can there be something believable at the roof of this?"
And just to give you some small defense of that approach,
I always like to ask students, "Suppose we didn't have a
single historical record, no newspaper,
no diaries. You know nothing totally
reliable for what happened in the latter part of the
eighteenth century in America." Would we know anything about
what happened? Of course, we would.
We would know that there was a revolution;
it was against Great Britain. I'm sure we would know that the
French assisted in that. I am certain we would know that
George Washington was the commander of our forces in our
battle. Those are easy.
There's no getting around reading those things,
and then it gets to be more interesting as we speculate.
We would know as a fact that George Washington threw a silver
dollar across the Rappahannock River, except that it's
impossible. So, we would dismiss that one.
We would be told that he was very honest and told his father
he chopped down a cherry tree, which would be baloney,
but we would be told that too. But I think we would be told
also very many true things, which came down to us.
So, the hard job would be to select among these legendary
things, to see what fact can be found, and it will never be easy
or deadly certain. But that's what I'm talking
about here. Finally,
there is the source that people who are skeptical most like to
believe because it's tangible. I'm talking about archaeology,
which is the discovery, examination,
and evaluation of material evidence,
which is not in writing, the actual remains of places
where they lived, the implements that they used
and so on, and so on.
And the beautiful thing about that is you actually have it.
It's objective. It's an object.
It's not something that somebody imagined,
but you shouldn't derive as much confidence from it as a lot
of archaeologists like to, because it's only a thing until
you say what it means, until you put a date on it,
until you try to understand what it really is,
what its function was, who brought it there,
who left it there. All those things have to be
reasoned out from all the evidence, all the information
you can get. So there's an astonishing
amount of speculation involved in establishing this apparently
rigorous objective technique. We certainly need to use it and
we need to use it as carefully, that's my point,
as we use everything else. But it is indeed very valuable
in studying a world before our time, always.
Now, we mentioned how important the poems are.
So, we need to take a look at the question of what they are,
and how we know about them, and so on.
I mentioned to you that the Iliad and the Odyssey
were known in the Western world continuously from the time that
they were made available. So they were known and they
were very important in the minds of those people who knew about
it, but I also mentioned last time
the impact of Schliemann's excavations, which turned
everything around. The hyper-skeptical point of
view taken by scholars in Europe in the nineteenth century was
eroded very sharply by the discovery of places that really
convinced pretty much everybody that there was a Troy,
and that there was a Mycenae. And so the stories couldn't
have been simple inventions, and that began a new phase in
the story. And, again, to repeat what I
said last time, there were certain stunning
physical resemblances between what Homer said and what we
could see. The palaces were like the
palaces that he described. The world that they lived in
was a world in which bronze was used for implements,
and weapons, and such, not iron,
and that squared with what was found in Mycenae,
what was found in the Mycenaean world, namely bronze implements
and fundamentally not iron ones. Sometimes there were
interesting little problems that emerged and one of those has to
do with the use of chariots in warfare.
Well, Homer has his heroes using chariots and we know that
chariots were used in warfare in the Bronze Age around the
Mediterranean Sea. We have hard evidence of that
in Egypt, in Asia Minor, and in the Tigris Euphrates
Valley. So, you would say,
well, that's another place where Homer got it right,
except for the fact that we also know how chariots are used
in warfare and the closest analogy,
I think, is to think of chariots as tanks.
You know, one famous tactic is--if you have an infantry
force coming forward, you send tanks in it to break
up the line of the infantry, so that you can defeat the
infantry in that way. And apparently that is the way
you use chariots in ancient Bronze Age warfare.
You would send the chariot racing toward the line of
infantrymen and the usual outcome was the infantrymen
would panic in the face of being charged by these things,
and you would break their line and give the other side an
opportunity to wreak havoc with their army.
Well, what do the Homeric heroes do with their chariots?
They use them as taxicabs.
Achilles or Patroclus, or whoever is on his chariot,
is driving. He is riding from the ships or
wherever he is from the camp to the battlefield.
He might pick up a missile of some kind, a spear typically,
and fire it at somebody as he goes by.
This would be a drive by killing, but then when he really
gets to where the action is he hops off--now we're going to
have some fighting. And so, the implication I
think is that the memory of chariot warfare back in the
Mycenaean days lingered; it was captured in the poetry
that goes back--the bits of the poetry that goes back to the
Mycenaean period. But how they were used was
forgotten, and so the poets in the subsequent years then
thought, "How would I use a
chariot?"--never having seen a chariot fight in a battle,
and that's the outcome. Finley, particularly,
makes a lot of this as being rather indicative of how he
pictures the poems to work. There are sort of legitimate
memories, some of them going way back to the Mycenaean period,
but which may be misremembered in some significant detail.
And then, of course, there's lots of stuff that
doesn't have anything to do with the Mycenaean period.
His view is much, if not most,
of what we are told about the Homeric world comes,
as he says, in the tenth and in the ninth centuries.
One other thing that he doesn't mention but I think is
worth mentioning. Many a scholar are very
reluctant to admit that there's any Mycenaean stuff here,
although they cannot fail to concede that some of the
physical implements that are found at Mycenaean sites are
precisely like what Homer says. But I think you can go a little
bit beyond that. Some scholars have pointed out
that in Book II of the Iliad in the section that we
call, "The Catalog of Ships," the
poet lays out just exactly how many warships came to Troy from
Greece, and just exactly how many came
from each town. And the names of the towns that
are listed in that catalog of ships, first of all,
are all legitimate in the sense every one of them we know did
exist in the Mycenaean Period. And perhaps no less significant
is that there are also towns listed there that are Mycenaean
towns, which disappeared after the Mycenaean Period.
In other words, they couldn't just have named
towns that used to be Mycenaean, but were still around,
so that's why they knew them. No, some towns had disappeared,
but the names of those towns show up in the catalog of ships.
There's just no way to explain that except to say that catalog
of ships goes back to the Mycenaean Period.
Now, the differences between what we find in the
Homeric poems are also very illuminating,
differences between that and what we know happened after the
fall of the Mycenaean world. For instance,
one of the most striking things that you find in cultures,
anthropologists and archaeologists live off this,
is what they do with dead bodies.
Now, in Mycenae, it's obvious; they bury them in the ground as
most of us do. The graves in the circle,
the shaft graves, and then the beehive tombs for
the big shots, and even outside in the
countryside, we find graves which have bones of people in
them. But we know that the Greeks in
Homer don't do that. The Greeks in Homer incinerate
the bodies of the dead. You remember the Iliad
ends with the actual cremation of the bodies of the relevant
people. So, that's a very significant
difference. That memory had simply died out
and it helps us to remember too that the tombs that we have seen
now, they didn't see. Whoever was writing the poems
of Homer, whichever poets were contributing to that over the
ages after the Mycenaean Period, they hadn't seen those
Mycenaean sites. They were buried.
There are also differences, sometimes, in the shape of
weapons that we find in the Greek World after the Mycenaean
Period compared to what are described in Homer's poems.
I'm sorry. Homer describes certain of
these weapons, which don't fit what we find in
the ground. And here's another critical
element in the story.
We know that the Mycenaeans, or at least some small number
of them could write, because we have the Linear B
script, which we can read. There is no clue that there is
such a thing as writing in the Homeric poems.
There's one very abstruse clue where somebody seems to know
something about it, but fundamentally it's an
illiterate society and that is a major difference between the
world of Homer and the Mycenaean world.
Some other differences: Homer's kings,
if you just see how they live, what they do,
what their wives do, how they are treated by their
fellow noblemen, they are,
in a relative sense, very weak, very short on power
and really quite poor compared to these Mycenaean kings,
the results of whose work and lives we see at places like
Mycenae. Remember,
I tried to emphasize how rich you would have to be to
undertake the building of the temple,
to undertake the construction of one of those beehive tombs.
You had to be very confident because it was going to take a
long time, a fantastic amount of labor, a tremendous amount of
money to do that. There is no evidence in Homer
that anybody had that kind of wealth or that kind of power.
What do the queens in Homer do in their spare time?
Or maybe it's not their spare time, maybe it's their regular
time. Well, one of the things that
they do when the Homeric heroes refer to their wives--there are
really only two places that they seem to be associated with.
One is the bedroom and the other is the loom.
What these ladies are doing is weaving cloth.
Now, that's not what queens do. I'm sure the Mycenaean queens
didn't do that, but it's very,
very interesting that that is what the Homeric queens do.
Well, how are we to explain the discrepancies that are so great
between these worlds? And the answer that almost
everybody now accepts without argument is that these poems
were created orally, and passed on orally.
That they were not written down, so that what we have in
the poems of Homer reflects centuries of bards passing on
bits of the poem, or the poem in various
versions, being always creative. I mean, any bard,
if by analogy we know about bards in the modern world,
we have some evidence on that. Millman Parry,
a Harvard scholar back in the twenties, went to Yugoslavia to
live in the mountains and the backwoods,
and he lived with people who still had these bards around who
created sort of epic narratives of considerable length,
but nothing resembling Homeric length, I must say.
Nothing that long, but long enough in which they
would tell the same stories in verse and music,
and you could recognize the story as you went from bard to
bard. But every bard added and
subtracted things to suit his own talents.
That's the idea of the game, and then Parry demonstrated by
careful scholarship of the Homeric poems,
that that is the way the Homeric poems were.
I want to use the word stitched together, because in the Ancient
Greek world the people who sang, recited, created the poems of
the Homeric epics were called rhapsodes,
and that means stitchers of songs.
So, what you have to imagine is sometime back,
I would argue, in the Mycenaean Period,
somebody began making up one of these songs, telling the story
of Greeks going to attack the city of Troy.
And that for centuries thereafter, different
rhapsodes repeated it but elucidated it,
illuminated it, extended it,
changed it, tried to improve it, sometimes they added stuff.
They were alive in the tenth century.
Some of them were alive in the ninth and certainly some of them
were alive in the time of Homer in the eighth.
So that what we have before us, is that kind of product and
that will explain both the similarities and the
differences, and that is what underlies our
interpretation of how the poems got to be what they were.
So, what is this world like that emerges from the world of
Homer? We don't have to make up our
minds in advance whether it was a real world or a completely
fantastic one, but at least let's see if we
can describe what world it looks like.
And I'm going to focus my attention on what you might call
the political side of that society as it reveals itself in
the poems. We hear about key individuals,
and the last time I mentioned to you two words,
I think I did, but I'll mention them again
this time. The head of the expedition to
Troy, Agamemnon, the sort of
generalissimo of that expedition is called
wanax. When you drop the "w" as later
Greek dialects did, it becomes anax.
He, so far as I know, and I think I'm not forgetting,
he is the only human being referred to in the poems in that
way. There are, however,
many an individual in the poem who is referred to as a
basileus, the plural is basileis,
which is normally and regularly translated as king,
and that's right. For instance,
in historical times when the Greeks referred to the great
King of Persia, who was a real king and a
powerful figure, a king in every sense,
the word they used for him was basileus.
But we quickly see that the people referred to as
basileus in Homer are not like the great King of Persia.
They are much lesser figures. I'll come back to that in just
a moment. The Mycenaean kings we
know, thanks to the Linear B tablets, were referred to,
the singular once again is wanax,
and the plural is wanaktes.
But in Homer the term is reserved for Agamemnon or for
gods, but not for any other human being.
And that raises the question, why is Agamemnon wanax?
And that, I think, we have to understand as being
because of his function in the situation,
namely there is a multi-city invasion of Troy being carried
on by these Mycenaean Greeks. Agamemnon has been chosen as
the generalissimo and that is what gives him,
temporarily, the title of wanax.
I would imagine and I'm very confident that after the war of
Troy, if Agamemnon had been allowed by his wife to live for
more than a few minutes after he set foot at home,
he would no longer be called wanax,
but would be called basileus like the other
rulers of their local towns. You remember I suggested that
in the Linear B tablets when there was a reference to a
basileus, he's clearly well below the
wanax and some scholars suggest, in a persuasive way,
I think, that these basileus may have been
village chieftains but that's as high as they got.
But it's very interesting that when you get to historical
Greece, as we shall see, there are no wanaktes
but there are, at least according to
tradition, basileis.
But no basileus has anything like the clout that the
Mycenaean kings did, and of course we don't hear of
any of them who have even the temporary special power that
Agamemnon has. No human being is referred to
as wanax in the period of historical Greece.
And of course, the kings when we see them in
Homer do not have a bureaucracy, do not have scribes.
How could there be scribes? They didn't know how to write.
There are no inventories. These are not rich guys with
fantastic quantities of stuff that has to be cataloged and
inventoried. The kings, by our standards for
kings, are really very poor. What do they do in their spare
time or in their time in general?
They, themselves, engage in agriculture.
I don't mean they dig in the ground, but they supervise it;
they think about it. They are like people who are in
charge of a plantation, their own plantation,
I mean. So, that's one of their
activities. You cannot imagine the great
kings of Mycenae doing that. They would've had all kinds of
subordinate officials taking care of that.
Another thing that these kings are seen to do,
which is in a way even at a lower level, is to be herdsmen.
Again, not themselves out there with the goats and the sheep,
but they are referred to as having these herds and having to
cope with them. Another very popular,
I would say the most popular activity among the kings,
was piracy. That's what they brag about.
Achilles, my God, what a king he is!
He sacked 24 cities. Why do you sack a city?
To steal what they have and, well, there are all kinds of
wonderful examples of people in the Iliad and the
Odyssey. Some stranger comes,
this is in the Odyssey, and they ask him,
"Sir, are you a pirate?" And he says,
"No, no, I'm not a pirate," just like they asked,
I mean, "Do you come from Chicago?"
He wasn't insulted. "No, I'm not a pirate,
but I could've been, of course.
We understand that."
And then later on in the story that Homer tells in the
Odyssey, Odysseus himself is such a
newcomer. He's taken to the beautiful
city on the island of Scheria, Phaiacia, and is treated with
great respect as you're supposed to in the Mycenaean world.
But after dinner, they do what they do to amuse
themselves. They have athletic contests and
they ask Odysseus to participate.
And he says, "No, no, I'm too miserable and
wretched," and the guy says, "Oh, you must be some kind of a
merchant." And Odysseus says that that was
a black remark. Those are fighting words.
You can't call--we know Odysseus himself is a
basileus--him a merchant. Pirate, sure, but merchant, no.
Another thing that is interesting is that when you
look at the burials of Greeks in the post-Mycenaean period,
in the Dark Ages, there's nothing resembling
those grand tombs and the wealth that's buried in them for the
dead. You find that the tombs of
noblemen are very much the same one as the other.
You're struck by the equality from the standpoint of riches of
the dead nobility. No great distinction and no
great riches either. You're dealing with a poorer
world and a world that doesn't have this kind of outstanding
monarchy. So, one of the things I think
we learn is that the Homeric world of the kings,
the role of the kings, the wealth of the kings,
the power of the kings, the place of the kings is not
taken from the Mycenaean period. If it's describing anything
that's real, it's describing very clearly a post-Mycenaean
world in those Dark Ages that we have been talking about.
But another thing that crops up is that in the
Iliad and the Odyssey,
you get a very clear picture, really of what is the political
structure of each society. And by the way,
you must keep in mind a very important difference between
the Iliad and the Odyssey;
the Iliad takes place at Troy.
None of these noblemen, none of these kings,
none of these heroes is back home in his own town ruling it.
He is at war and he is serving under a commander,
and so the behavior of these people towards one another is
not precisely like what it would be.
And here you see in the Odyssey is what it would
likely be, and the place where you see it is back in Ithaca
when Odysseus is there or when we're taken to see what's going
on. I think that's a very important
distinction to make, but even when they're at Troy
and in this sort of non-typical situation,
we still see the same institutions working,
the same relationships being present as would be present at
home, although you have to watch out
for the difference. What do I mean?
How are decisions made? Does the king simply say,
"Do it," and it gets done? Nothing like that.
The king has got important powers.
Agamemnon as the chief out there in the Iliad,
he can call a meeting of the assembly,
I should say of the council, but he's not the only one who
can. Any nobleman who wants to can
say, "We ought to have a council," and then that council
will come together and do whatever business they wish to
do. The council,
however, is limited to noblemen, to these
basileis. Ordinary soldiers do not
attend, and that's one of the things I think we must grasp
immediately. The key line in the society of
the Dark Ages appears to be certainly not between monarchy
and everybody else, but between nobility and
commoners. That's the really important,
serious line--certainly politically and in other ways as
well. There is, however,
in Homer, an assembly that consists of the men,
in the case of Troy of course the fighting men who are there,
but who are not basileus. But also in the home,
at home, the men of fighting age and condition.
They are the only ones who matter.
Of course, as in all of the rest of Greek history,
women are excluded from the political realm,
and of course, well, I'll just leave it at
that. But so, too,
there's obviously an age limit. You have to be of an age to be
a fighting man. It's not necessarily defined
for us. It depends, could have been 18,
could have been 20. In Athens, in classical times
it was 20.
Well, let me just remind you of some events that show you
how these things work. Remember, the Iliad
starts because of a quarrel and the quarrel emerges from the
fact that the Greeks are busily being killed by a terrible
plague that has struck them. They say, "We got to find out
what's happening?" They always assume that if
something like that happened, it was some god or gods who was
angry with them. So, they get a seer who goes
and is persuaded to try to find out what's happening.
And he finally does ascertain that Apollo is angry with the
Greeks because Agamemnon took a maiden from her father,
and that father was a priest of Apollo.
And so when this is ascertained, Achilles,
the biggest, bravest, strongest,
fastest hero on the Greek side, intervenes and says,
"Well, look, why don't you give back the
girl and then Apollo will stop killing us and everything will
be okay?" Agamemnon gets furious with
Achilles and he says, "No, I'm not giving back my
girl. I'm the boss here," as Edward
G. Robinson used to say.
How many of you ever heard of Edward G.
Robinson? Just raise your hand, please.
Good, put me in my place. It gets worse every year for me.
And Achilles then speaks up and really lets him have it,
chews him out, tells him what a bozo he is,
and, you know, the very important thing is
this. How can you do that if this is
a king? And the answer is:
you can do that because you're both kings.
There is nothing out of line in the sense of violating some kind
of a real rule of the society, but it's not typical,
and especially since Agamemnon has this position as the boss,
the most kingly of the kings. That's a word that Homer uses
of him, basileutatos, the most kingly,
and that's because of his position.
So, Achilles is not doing anything sort of illegal or
unconstitutional, but he's doing something that's
really out of line from a normal point of view.
And finally Agamemnon says, "No, I'm not going to give back
my girl, but I'll tell you what,
I will give back my girl if I am given the girl you took from
a different Trojan, and that'll be fine.
I'll have your girl and you won't have any."
So now, Achilles really blows his top and from the quarrel,
and finally when he says, "Okay, if that's what you're
going to do to me, I'm taking my armor and I'm
going home." And off he goes,
and he sulks in his tent for the next nine books,
and this turns out to be a serious problem for them.
But, what you learn from that is that the way decisions
are made, important decisions are made,
even in this army, is by discussion among the
basileis, among the noblemen,
and you will try to reach a consensus about these things,
and in an extreme odd situation like this,
it would have to be that they would have to do what the
commander says. And probably back home there
would be the implication that if you can't work things out among
them with consensus, probably the king has some
weight. But what we have to remember is
he can't give orders to anybody typically, although Agamemnon
can get away with it on this expedition.
Well, that's one story. Another story that we're
told is that soon afterwards also in that same place in
the Iliad, a dream comes to Agamemnon,
because, you know, this is their tenth year.
They've been trying to take this city for nine years.
It's almost as bad as Iraq and the soldiers are tired of all of
this. If we can't take the city,
we ought to go home and there's a lot of spirit that says we
ought to go home. And so a dream comes to
Agamemnon. The god says to him,
"Here's what you need to do. You need to try the spirit of
your men, and in that way to inspirit them to carry on until
victory. So, what you should do is to
get up and speak to your soldiers, and say that you're
never going to take Troy. You might as well pack up and
go home, and then they'll say, 'No, king, no,
we receive to do that. We insist on staying.
We're going to re-up and do another term,
and we're going to take the city.'"
So, Agamemnon says, "Great, I'll do that," and he
calls the troops together to battle, and he makes his little
speech. I wish I could reproduce the
Homer. I didn't take it along with me,
but the essence of it is a great roar and rumble emerged as
the troops turned and began racing back to the ships to get
the hell out of there. Just to carry on some of
the highlights, that tells us a lot about the
society. So, as they're roaring back,
suddenly Odysseus, the slyest, the cleverest,
the smartest of all of the Greeks,
he goes racing among the troops who are heading back and he
grabs one, and Homer says when he came to a gentleman,
a basileus, he would say,
"Sir, you are making a mistake. You don't understand the game
that Agamemnon is playing," and he explains it to him,
and the guy says, "Oh, okay."
When he comes to one of the common sort, he says,
"You bloody imbecile, get the hell back to where you
belong." That's a rough translation and
everybody finally grabs enough of them and the thing turns
around, everybody goes back and sits down.
And up steps one man.
Homer describes him as the ugliest man in the entire army.
So you get a clue as to what we're supposed to think about
him, and he makes a speech which denounces all of the
basileus, Agamemnon ahead of any of them.
He says, "We ordinary soldiers have had enough and we would
like to go home." And up steps Odysseus and
blasts him with his scepter, smashes him across the back,
leaving a welt that could be seen by the entire army,
and tears came to the eyes of this guy.
Are we supposed to feel sorry for him?
Well, the next lines in Homer say that one soldier popped up
and said, "Of all the great things Odysseus has done for us
here, that was the greatest,
to shut up a big mouth idiot like Thersites."
Well, what Thersites had done that was wrong,
of course the poet and Odysseus didn't like his policy
suggestion, but he had no right to speak at all.
The only people who could speak in the council or in an assembly
were the noblemen, the basileis.
So, he had crossed the line as an ordinary soldier.
To rise and to say anything was a violation of the culture,
and that's one of the places where you see where this sharp
line exists. They just take orders,
but the gentlemen don't just take orders.
They can argue and sometimes they can win the argument.
So, what you see in this very brief and inadequate account
that I've given you is that we really,
in spite of the fact that we have basileis,
and even in this case an anax,
we really don't have a proper monarchical tradition.
When we think of monarchs, single rulers,
we think of Hammurabi and we think of the kings of Persia,
and we think of Louis XIV. We do not think of what we have
here, which is a bunch of noblemen who are essentially
equal, and the differences between
them don't come from birth or rank as between them,
but from wealth and power that they happen to possess.
It is, rather, not a royal society but an
aristocratic society. I think that's the main message
and it is the matrix of all future political ideas and
arguments in the Greek world that comes after this time.
I think you need to understand that what the Greeks in the
historical period--once we start having written records by the
Greeks themselves, the thing that is the standard
position--what is this thing on the computer when you fall back
to a position? What do you call that position?
What is it? Default, that's right.
Good, the default position in Greek political theory is
aristocracy; that is the normal thing.
A very good example of that is what I've been telling you;
that's really what happens. And here's another thing,
if you go to the end of the Greek story, when you think
about political theory, there's Plato,
and when he lays out the ideal society in his view,
in the Republic, we find there are multiple
rulers. And these, of course,
turn out to be the winners of the Jeopardy contest playoffs.
But it doesn't matter. There's never one king.
It's always a group of people that is the best government,
and they will be the best. In this case defined chiefly by
their intelligence, but other things too.
Well, anyway in this case, in Greek political thinking the
aristocracy of birth is the default position.
Anybody who wants to argue for a different kind of political
arrangement will have to make the case uphill against all
tradition. I hope that you'll have that in
the back of your head when we get to the story of Athens and
the invention of democracy, because it was off the wall
from the perspective of Greek tradition.
And of course, anybody from time to time,
there are individuals who thought that monarchy might be a
fine thing. They ran against something that
was regarded with much more hostility by the Greeks.
When they're through and had reached their peak,
their notion of monarchy is something fit for barbarians,
but not for Greeks. A free man may not live under a
monarchy, and the roots of that, I think, are visible in Homer.
In passing, I just want to say that Homer, of course,
is the basic text, the basic document for all
Greek thinking in every area that you can imagine throughout
the rest of Greek history. Over time, it becomes not the
only one, but it never ceases to be the best known,
the most influential, and the most powerful.
If it were a religious document primarily we would speak of it
as the Greek Bible, but it isn't.
Well, some examples, later on in history there's a
quarrel between Athens and Megara as to who controls the
island of Salamis. They decide to call in an
arbitrator. So, they call in the Spartans,
and the Spartans say, "Okay, we'll decide," and they
decide that it belongs to Athens.
Why? Well, if you look at the
catalog of ships in Homer's Iliad,
the island of Salamis had its ships lined up next to the
island of Athens. Ballgame.
You have to realize how potent this is.
Well, let me turn to another aspect of the story of
Homer and how the poems play into Greek society.
I want to talk to you about the ethics and values that emerge
from the reading of the Iliad and the
Odyssey. I mentioned religion and so we should take a
look first at the gods. We are talking,
first of all, and remember about a
multi-deity society. Polytheism is what we're
talking about. That is true of all of human
societies that we know anything about down to the earliest
possible exception, I suppose;
well, it depends what you think is earliest.
You could say the Hebrews are the earliest,
pure and simple, but depending on how you date
biblical things, there's an outside chance that
an Egyptian pharaoh in the sixteenth century B.C.,
I think, might have claim to have some such state.
But otherwise, there is no such thing.
So, this is a polytheistic society with heroic
characteristics. That is, this kind of
aristocratic outfit, aristocracy of birth,
which is legitimized by heroic behavior on the battlefield.
Now, one of the things the Greeks believed,
as we discover from a poem written by one of their major
poets, is something so far as I know
unique to the Greeks. They claimed that they were of
the same race as the gods, and I really don't know of
anybody else who made that claim.
And so you will hear Homeric characters referred to by
epithets, Homer, part of the technique of
passing on oral poetry is by having epithets attached to the
rulers to help with the meter. Some hero will be called
dios, meaning godly, god-like, diotrephes,
reared as a god, isothesos,
equal unto a god, and there are others as well.
Now, mind you, notice these are not people
referred to as god-fearing or lovers of god,
no. They are just about equal to
the gods according to these terms.
Now, that on the one hand is this extraordinary claim that
the Greeks make. They did make amazingly
powerful claims for human beings as opposed to divinity,
compared to any society that I know anything about.
This is part of the arrogance that is characteristic of the
Ancient Greeks, but at the same time,
and right away at the beginning we're getting to such a very
Greek thing, a Greek characteristic.
At the same time that he is this great thing almost like a
god, he is also not a god in the most crucial way possible.
Gods do not die. Men die.
The mortality of the human being is a reality and it's of
the greatest significance and importance,
and of course men are not as strong and as powerful as the
gods. And indeed, as we shall see,
well, the tragic view of life, which the Greeks invent and
which characterizes their culture,
is there right at the beginning in the Iliad and the
Odyssey. It says that at the same time as man is a
remarkable, marvelous creature capable of
all sorts of amazing things, even unto being almost like the
gods, he is nonetheless mortal and
dies, and he doesn't have the power that the gods do.
And what do you do about that?
Well, it's interesting, I think, to compare the Greek
way of dealing with this human problem that we all have,
the problem of death. How do we deal with the fact
that we will die? Well, there's what I like to
call the Eastern solution that you find in many an Eastern
religion and philosophy that says that man is,
in fact, nothing. He is dust.
He is dung depending on which story you listen to.
So, of course you're going to die.
Who cares? Why should you care?
You were nothing to begin with; you'll be nothing when you're
finished. Relax.
Then there is what I would characterize as the Christian
solution. You're worried about dying?
You need not die. If you are a good Christian and
you do all the things that you need to do to be a good
Christian, you will not die. You will have personal
immortality. So that's how you get around
that problem. No need to worry if you're
doing things right. Well, somehow Christians
continued to worry and we have a millennium of them killing each
other about how you're supposed to worry about these things.
But if you can accept the purity of the statement I just
made, it is at the root of the thing you have a solution.
But the Greek tragic view does not take either of these
routes, which I regard as a relatively easy escape from the
problem compared to the way the Greeks got stuck.
Man is great and they keep saying so.
He is important. He is capable of great things.
He is of the same race as the gods, and at the same time his
life is short and death is final, and death is bad.
I ought to say a word about death, in order to comprehend
what the Greeks thought. You know, different peoples
have had different ideas about them.
Sometimes the notion is that it is just terrible for everybody
with actual pain and suffering, and others have a notion of a
wonderful kind of a heaven in which marvelous things happen to
you, sometimes spiritual,
sometimes physical depending on the religion.
But for the Greeks, as I think for quite a few
other people in the ancient world, death was nothing in the
worst sense of the word. You just went somewhere and
there was nothing. There was darkness.
There was nothing at all. Some few people who had
sinned terribly and earned the wrath of the gods would,
indeed, be tortured in some special and typically Greek,
interesting way. You remember Tantalus.
He had done a terrible thing and there he stood forever with
his feet in the water below, and above him a tree with
grapes hanging down, and dying of thirst.
And every time he went down to try to sip some of the water,
the water receded, and anytime he reached up for
the grapes, the grapes were pulled back.
That is a Greek idea of hell, where you got to keep trying
and you always lose. So, that's the picture and you
have to realize that death is a bad thing.
In the Odyssey, Odysseus has reason to go down
to Hades, and while he's down there he comes upon Achilles who
has died. And he says,
"Well, it's good to see you, Achilles.
Say, you look fine. You must really be doing okay
down here. I know that you are a judge
down here and much respected. So, looks like you've beaten
the rap." And Achilles says,
"Odysseus, don't say a word to me about the virtues of death.
Better to be a serf, the lowest serf on the earth,
than to be a king in Hades." Now, that's as bad as it can
possibly be. The great Achilles,
respected still in the afterworld would immediately
turn it in to be a complete nobody on earth.
So, it's very important. They faced without any real
retreat the reality and the negative character of death,
even as they refused to reject the significance of life or of
mankind. That is what I mean when I
speak of the tragic view, and it's very important.
Now, it seems to me we can eliminate that a little bit by
comparing it with various modern approaches to the same sorts of
problems. We haven't gotten rid of those
problems yet, in spite of modern medicine.
We live, still, I think in what might be called
the Age of the Enlightenment. That is the dominant sort of
paradigm of what life is all about, at least in the Western
world and a good deal more of it where the West has had an
influence. At the core of it is a belief
in progress, something that was essentially not present among
the Greeks.
Progress in the eyes of the philosophers of the eighteenth
century, though they would have been very angry to hear me say
this, was something like the
equivalent of the Christian hope for immortality.
The hope of the Voltaires of this world was that they could
make the world better constantly by their efforts,
and this would be rewarded in a kind of a way,
because progress in the future after they were gone would
redound to their credit for having brought it about.
And that in some sense they would live on in this society
which they had improved and made a better thing.
Another aspect that is very important in this sort of
enlightenment approach is individualism,
that the core of everything is the single individual person.
As we shall see, this is very different from the
Greeks. Now, the Greeks were very much
concerned individuals and this is especially true of the
democrats in Athens. But even their most potent
spokesman and leader placed the goals, and achievements,
and everything else of an individual behind something that
they thought was more important, which was the community at
large, which, in historical times was the
polis. Well, that's not the way it is
with the modern world and that's not the way it comes out of the
enlightenment, the individual is the ultimate.
The enlightenment, if you go back to its routes in
the seventeenth century with the likes of Hobbes and Locke--what
is the ultimate place you go to? It is the rights of individuals.
You may not stamp out the rights of individuals.
They are inherent in everything. Either you believe,
as our founding father said that we were endowed with them
by our creator. They didn't say God because,
of course, the Enlightenment thinkers were not so sure they
believed in God, but they still seemed to
believe in something they wanted to call a creator.
Or if you didn't believe in God, this was just a natural
right. Nature gave each individual the
right to life, liberty, property,
and nobody could take these away legitimately.
Well, the Greeks had no concept of natural rights,
or of rights that human beings were given by the gods.
That is a very important difference that was,
you had to act in such a way as to make life possible and
decent, and for the Greeks that always
meant being part of a decent community, the polis.
But the modern world, to get back to that,
to this Enlightenment world, individualism and a key aspect
to that is hedonism. That is to say,
it is legitimate and proper to search for pleasure,
for each individual to attempt to please himself however he
can. And it turns out that if you
could take it to our own day, there are no limits pretty much
to what he can do to gain pleasure.
I would argue that there is a direct line from the
Enlightenment philosophy to nihilism,
that is to say a philosophy that says there are no limits to
what human beings may do. What turns out to be the
practical fact is that he who has the power and the will to do
what he wants will be able to do so,
and he who has not will be forced to suffer whatever the
powerful impose on him. And this is seen by the
original nihilists as a good thing.
What's his name, Nietzsche, of course,
said, "Some of us are better than others.
Some of us are supermen, and it is quite wrong and
wicked for us to be treated as though we were ordinary fellows,
and therefore do not tie us down with these ridiculous codes
of ethics, and morals, and other things which are
simply the weapons by which the weak hold down the strong."
This was an interesting idea, but it wasn't new.
There's a Greek in the fifth century who says the same thing.
There is no definition of goodness for this modern
approach, no definition of happiness.
Each individual decides for himself what is good,
what is happy. What it really does is to evade
the question that I'm talking about.
Is this all okay? If we're all going to die then
does it really mean that we should just do the best we can
at anybody's expense while we're alive?
Is that a satisfactory outcome? Will we indeed be happier,
better off while we're alive? If we do that,
the Greeks would have said, "That is stupid and absurd to
think for ten seconds you'll realize that's no good."
Now, the Greeks on the other hand had a powerful belief
in the dominance of chance. They accepted,
again, what is a very modern idea now, that in fact there is
no divine force or divine forces who oversee what happens to
mankind on earth. But, rather,
things happen simply in a random way according to no
particular rule and that's the way it is.
It is not virtue or merit that determine the quality of your
life. It is chance,
and there are several places in the Iliad and the
Odyssey that emphasize that point.
Well, that leaves the Greeks with something like this
question. In the light of human
mortality, the disinterest of the gods, the chanciness of
life, what can man do to achieve happiness and immortality?
Because he still doesn't feel happy about his mortality.
Though he accepts that this is a problem, it's something that
he still hankers after. It's inevitable that people
should, and part of the answer is very Homeric.
It is the heroic ethic. At a certain place,
I think a couple of places in the Iliad,
Achilles answers the question, "Why did you come here to fight
at Troy?" We know the legend says that
Achilles was told before he came that if he did not go to Troy
and fight in that war, because his mother was a
goddess, he had partial divinity in him, he would be immortal.
He would never die. But, on the other hand,
he would not be great and famous.
His memory would not be carried forward into the future.
If he went to Troy, he would die,
but his memory as the greatest of the Achaeans would be
immortal forever. Well, you know the choice he
took and you know that it turned out to be right.
We still know about Achilles, don't we?
And when we're all gone, people will know about
Achilles. So, we should take the Greeks
very seriously on that score. Well, anyway,
sometimes he's asked, "What made you come here in
spite of that?" and his answer was,
"Well, when my father sent me here, he told me a number of
things that I'm supposed to do, but the most important of these
was the Greek words, aien aristeioi,
always be the Best. The best doesn't mean morally
the best in anything like our sense.
It means the greatest, the strongest,
the ablest, the most admired. That is what you want to be.
Well, you can only do that if you are in a contest.
You can only be the best if somebody is not as good,
and the Greek word for that kind of a contest is
agon, and so it's fair to think about
the Greeks, I think it's very necessary to think about the
Greeks as having a particular agonal society,
a society filled with competition, in which if not
everybody, lots and lots of people are constantly striving
to be the very best, whatever the definition of best
is in the context that's relevant.
Now, I guess I'm out of time. So, I'll pick up the story next
time with the story about this heroic ethic and the impact that
it has on Greek society.
Mobile Analytics